THE NEW REALISM THE MACMILLAN COMPANY . NEW YORK • BOSTON • CHICAGO DALLAS • SAN FRANCISCO MACMILLAN & CO., LIMITED LONDON • BOMBAY • CALCUTTA MELBOURNE THE MACMILLAN CO. OF CANADA, LTD. TORONTO THE NEW REALISM COOPERATIVE STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY BY EDWIN B. HOLT WALTER T. MARVIN WILLIAM PEPPERRELL MONTAGUE RALPH BARTON PERRY WALTER B. PITKIN AND EDWARD GLEASON SPAULDING THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 1912 All rights reserved COPYRIGHT, 1912, BY THE MACMILLAN COMPANY. Set up and electrotyped. Published August, 1912. Norinooti J. 8. Cashing Co. — Berwick & Smith Co. Norwood, Mass., U.S.A. Ul -1VERSITY OF CALIFORNIA SANTA BARBAI^ ^. u.LEGE LIBRARY PREFACE ON July 21, 1910, we published a brief article entitled ' The Pro- gram and First Platform of Six Realists,' * in which we indicated the direction philosophical inquiry ought to take. We there asserted that advance would be facilitated by cooperative investigations ; and the drafting of the platform was a first attempt to confirm this belief. The present volume continues, on a larger scale, the work there inaugurated ; and we hope it will be followed by other col- lections of studies. The introductory essay voices our common opinions. The other essays do so only in part. It has seemed best to publish them with- out laboring for complete unanimity, inasmuch as their agreements quite overshadow their differences. They have been written after prolonged conferences. A few important debatable topics are briefly discussed by dissenting members in the Appendix. DECEMBER 31, 1911. 1 J. of Phil., Psychol., etc., 7, 393. This is reprinted in the Appendix. TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION SECTION PAGE I. THE HISTORICAL SIGNIFICANCE OF THE NEW REALISM ... 2 1. Naive realism, 2 — 2. Dualism, 4 — 3. Subjectivism of the Berkeleian type, 5 — 4. Subjectivism of the Kantian type, 8 — 5. The new realism, 9. II. THE REALISTIC POLEMIC ......... 11 1. The fallacy of argument from the ego-centric predicament, 11 — 2. The fallacy of pseudo-simplicity, 12 — 3. The fallacy of exclusive particularity, 14 — 4. The fallacy of definition by initial predication, 15 — 5. The speculative dogma, 16 — 6. The error of verbal suggestion, 18 — 7. The fallacy of illicit importance, 19. in. THE REALISTIC PROGRAM OF REFORM ...... 21 1. The scrupulous use of words, 21 — 2. Definition, 22 — 3. Analysis, 24 — 4. Regard for logical form, 25. — 5. Division of the question, 26 — 6. Explicit agreement, 28 — 7. The separa- tion of philosophical research from the study of the history of philosophy, 30. IV. REALISM AS A CONSTRUCTIVE PHILOSOPHY 31 1. Implications of the rejection of subjectivism, 32 — 2. Impli- cations of the rejection of anti-intellectualism, 32 — 3. Monism and pluralism, 33 — 4. Knowledge and its object; the independ- ence of the object, 33 — 6. Identity of content and thing known, 34 — 6. Platonic realism, 35 — 7. Summary, 36. V. REALISM AND THE SPECIAL SCIENCES ...... 36 1. The general attitude of realism to the special sciences, 36 — 2. Realism and psychology, 37 — 3. Realism and biology, 39 — 4. The relation of realism to logic and the mathematical sci- ences, 40 — 6. Realism as a basis for cooperation, 41. THE EMANCIPATION OF METAPHYSICS FEOM EPISTEMOLOGY BY WALTER T. MARVIN I. THE ISSUE BETWEEN DOGMATISM AND CRITICISM .... 45 1. Epistemology regarded as a science logically prior to all other sciences, 45 — 2. Epistemology regarded as a science of the limits viii TABLE OF CONTENTS SECTION PACK and possibility of knowledge, 46 — 3. Epistemology regarded as a theory of reality, 47 — 4. Summary, 49 — 5. The propositions held by the dogmatist in opposition to criticism, 49 — 6. The con- clusion which this essay will endeavor to establish, 50. II. THE THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE NOT LOGICALLY FUNDAMENTAL . 51 1. Two errors suspected to be present in the argument of the criticist, 51 — 2. Logic is not a science of the laws of thought, 52 — 3. The subject matter of logic, 52 — 4. This subject matter is non-mental, 52 — 5. Logic is not the art of correct thinking, 53 — 6. The way in which we use logic in our thinking, 54 — 7. Sum- mary, 65 — 8. Ambiguity of the word ' knowledge ' : the knowing process and the thing known, 56 — 9. The subsistence of proposi- tions, 57 — 10. Conclusion, 60. III. THE LOGICAL POSITION, RELATIVELY TO THE OTHER SCIENCES, OF THE THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE AND IN PARTICULAR OF THE PROBLEM OF THE POSSIBILITY OF KNOWLEDGE ... 60 1. The science of the possibility of knowledge presupposes logic, 60 — 2. The doctrine that the science of the possibility of knowl- edge is fundamental to all sciences other than logic, 61 — 3. Science itself and belief in the propositions of science do not presuppose the possibility of knowledge, 62 — 4. An ultimate premise is, as such, beyond investigation, 63 — 5. A restatement of the problem, 67 — 6. The theory of knowledge is logically subsequent to many of the special sciences, 67 — 7. So also is the science of the limits and possibility of knowledge, 70 — 8. Conclusion, 73. IV. EPISTEMOLOGY DOES NOT GIVE, BUT PRESUPPOSES A THEORY OF REALITY 74 1. Two types of transcendentalism, 74 — 2. Objections of the dogmatist to the first type of transcendentalism, 77 — 3. A brief examination of Kantian transcendentalism to illustrate these objec- tions, 78 — 4. Objections to the second type of transcendentalism : (a) reality a self-consistent system, 80 — 5. (ft) reality an organic unity, 82 — 6. Conclusion, 82. V. AN APPEAL TO THE PRAGMATIC TEST, TO THE VERDICT OF HISTORY 83 1. To what has the change in our modern conception of the world been due? 83 — 2. The influence of mathematics, 85 — 3. The influence of physics, 86 — 4. The influence of the doctrine of evolution and of historical research, 86 — 5. Influences at work in the doctrine of primary and secondary qualities, 87 — 6. Influ- ences at work in the doctrine of causation, 89 — 7. Influences at work in the doctrine of substance, 90 — 8. Influences at work in spiritualism and monistic absolutism, 91 — 9. Conclusion, 91. TABLE OF CONTENTS ix SECTION PAGE VI. METAPHYSICS SHOULD BE EMANCIPATED FROM EPISTEMOLOGY . . 92 1. The logical and methodological indebtedness of metaphysics to other bodies of knowledge, 92 — 2. Its indebtedness to episte- mology, 94 — 3. General conclusion, 94. A REALISTIC THEORY OF INDEPENDENCE BY EALPH BARTON PERRY I THE IMPORTANCE OF THE NOTION OF INDEPENDENCE ... 99 1. Its meaning in the older realism, 99 — 2. How used by Reid and Locke, 100 — 3. The resulting confusion of realism with sub- stantialism, 103 — 4. The present necessity of clarifying the con- cept, 104. II. MEANINGS OF THE TERM DEPENDENCE ...... 106 1. Relation, 106 — 2. Whole-part, 107—3. Part-whole, 107 — 4. Thing-attribute, 109 — 5. Attribute-thing, 109 — 6. Causation, 109 — 7. Reciprocity, 111 — 8. Implying, 112 — 9. Being implied, 112. III. THE MEANING OF INDEPENDENCE IN NEO-REALISM . . . .113 1. Independence not non-relation, 113 — 2. Independence not priority, 115 — 3. Independence denned, 117. IV. A REALISTIC THEORY OF INDEPENDENCE FORMULATED IN GENERAL TERMS 118 1. All simples mutually independent, 118 — 2. And independent of complexes of which they are members, 119 — 3. Complexes mutually independent, 119 — 4. Complexes dependent on their sim- ple constituents, 119 — 5. One case of a complex depending upon another, 119 — 6. Another case, 120 — 7. A third case, 121 — 8. A fourth case, 121 — 9. When one complex is independent of an- other, 122 — 10. How one entity may acquire dependence, 124. V. A REALISTIC THEORY OF INDEPENDENCE APPLIED TO THE CASE OF KNOWLEDGE 126 1. An experienced entity related to a complex, 126 — 2. Simple entities not dependent on consciousness, 126 — 3. Complexes inde- pendent of knowledge as respects their simple constituents, 129 — 4. Logical and mathematical propositions independent of con- sciousness, 129 — 5. Physical complexes independent of conscious- ness, 130 — 6. Logical, mathematical, and physical complexes as objects of consciousness, 132. VL CASES OF SUBJECTIVITY, OR DEPENDENCE ON A PRIMARY CONSCIOUS- NESS 136 1. Parts of consciousness dependent on the whole, 137 — 2. Lim- ited reciprocal dependence of parts of consciousness, 137 — TABLE OF CONTENTS 3. Some elements dependent on selective action, 138 — 4. And some on combining action, 139 — 5. Value dependent on con- sciousness, 140 — 6. Works of art, 141 — 7. History, society, life, and reflective thought, 142. VII. THE INDEPENDENCE OF SUBJECTIVITY ON A SECONDARY CONSCIOUS- NESS ..........'. 144 1. The subject of consciousness independent of being known, 144 — 2. One consciousness independent of another, 145 — 3. Mental content independent of introspection, 147 — 4. Value independent of value-judgments, 148 — 5. Perception independ- ent of reflection, 149. VIII. CONCLUSION 151 A DEFENSE OF ANALYSIS BY EDWARD GLEASON SPAULDING I. INTRODUCTORY 155 1. The types of analysis and of wholes, 155 — 2. What is analysis ? 167. II. COLLECTIONS AND ENUMEBATIVE ANALYSIS ..... 162 HI. THE SECOND TYPE OF WHOLE (SPACE, TIME, ETC.) AND ITS ANALYSIS 169 1. Arithmetical analysis, 173 — 2. Numbers, 173 — 3. Rational positive integers, 173 — 4. Relations, 175 — 5. Rational frac- tions, 177 — 6. Irrational and real numbers, 178 — 7. The analy- sis of space, 181 — 8. The analysis of time, 190 — 9. Motion and its analysis, 193 — 10. Velocity and acceleration, 204 — 11. Ac- celeration, 209 — 12. Dynamics and duration, 212 — 13. Other classes of individuals (atoms, etc.), 225. IV. PERCEPTUAL AND CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS 230 V. THE ANALYSIS OF ORGANIC WHOLES 237 1. Chemical compounds, etc., 237 — 2. Organisms and their analysis, 243. A REALISTIC THEORY OF TRUTH AND ERROR BY WILLIAM PEPPERRELL MONTAGUE . I. THE MEANING OF TRUTH AND ERROR ...... 252 1. Definition of true and false, 252 — 2. The meaning of real and unreal, 252 — 3. Objections to the definitions; the verbal TABLE OF CONTENTS xi SECTION PACK fallacy of psychophysical metonymy, 256 — 4. First consequences of the verbal fallacy of psycbophysical metonymy, 257 — 5. Sec- ond consequences of the verbal fallacy of psychophysical me- tonymy, 260 — 6. Summary, 262. II. CAUSALITY AND CONSCIOUSNESS IN A WORLD OF PURK FACT . . 263 1 Space, time, and quality as the ultimates of factual analysis, 263 — 2. The antinomy of causality — substantist thesis and posi- tivist antithesis, 264 — 3. The antinomy of consciousness — pan- hylist antithesis and panpsychist thesis, 268 — 4. A supplementary antinomy of consciousness ; are perceived objects inside or outside the brain? 276 — 5. Consciousness and causality; hylopsychism as the reciprocal solution of the two antinomies, 278 — 6. The three directions of a potentiality, 281 — 7. A certain difficulty in terminology, 282 — 8. The three levels of potentiality, 283 — 9. Summary, 285. III. THE GENESIS OF TRUTH AND ERROR ...... 286 1. The epistemological triangle, 286 — 2. The two kinds of truth and error, 289 — 3. Attention and belief, 292 — 4. The material fallacy of psychophysical metonymy, 294 — 5. Degrees of truth and error and the fallacy of internal relations, 297 — 6. Sum- mary, 300. THE PLACE OF ILLUSORY EXPERIENCE IN A REALISTIC WORLD BY EDWIN B. HOLT I. ILLUSIONS OF PERCEPTION AND THOUGHT ...... 303 1. Errors of space, 303 — 2. Errors of time, 307 — 3. Errors in secondary qualities, 308. — 4. Illusions of thought, 365. II. ERROR 357 1. Images assert nothing, 357 — 2. What the realist asserts, 358 — 3. Contradiction and being, 360 — 4. Contradiction and real- ism, 367. SOME REALISTIC IMPLICATIONS OF BIOLOGY BY WALTER B. PITKIN I. THE BIOLOGICAL ATTACK ON REALISM 378 II. FORMAL ANALYSIS OF THE BIOLOGICAL SITUATION .... 380 1. Simple description of some stimuli and reactions, 382 — A. Descriptive difference between stimuli and reactions, 382 — xii TABLE OF CONTENTS BECTION PA.GK B. Some types of reaction, 386 — a. Simple adjustment, 389 — b. Simple selection, 393 — c. Conduction, 396; the flatfish, 397 — d. Transformation, 405 — e. Resistances, 409 — i. Resist- ance by destruction of stimulus, 409 — ii. By interpolation, 411 — iii. By suspense of collateral functions, 412. HI. RESULTS OF THIS FORMAL ANALYSIS ...... 414 1. Perception non-constitutive, 416 — 2. No internal relations in organisms, 422 — 3. The total situation not reacted to, 424 — 4. Pure relations as stimuli, 425 — The fallacy of indiscernibles, 428. IV. SOME DEFECTS IN MODERN THEORIES OF CONSCIOUSNESS . . 434 1. The morphological fallacy, 434 — 2. The pragmatic point of view, 437 — 3. The new realistic analyses, 438 — 4. The biological point of view, 442. V. THE BIOLOGICAL STATUS OF CONSCIOUSNESS 443 1. The structure of the environment, 443 — 2. The environment as a space complex, 445 — 3. The factors of the biological situa- tion, 453 — 4. Projective indiscernibles, 458 — 5. Hallucinatory objects, 461 — 6. Conclusion, 466. APPENDIX Program and first platform of six realists, 471 — Montague on Holt, 480 — Holt on Montague, 482 — Pitkin on Montague and Holt, 483. INDEX . . 487 THE NEW REALISM INTRODUCTION » THE new realism may be said to be at the present moment some- thing between a tendency and a school. So long as it was recog- nized only by its enemies it was no more than a tendency. But war has developed a class-consciousness, .and the time is near at hand, if indeed it is not already here, when one realist may recog- nize another. This dawning spirit of fellowship, accompanied by a desire for a better understanding and a more effective co- operation, has prompted the present undertaking. It is perhaps inevitable that the new realism should for a time remain polemical in tone. A new philosophical movement in- variably arises as a protest against tradition, and bases its hope of constructive achievement on the correction of established habits of thought. Neo-realism is still in a phase in which this critical motive dominates, and is the chief source of its vigor and unanim- ity. Before, however, a philosophy can come of age, and play a major part in human thought, it must be a complete philosophy, or must at least show promise of completeness. If it is to assume the role, it must undertake to play the whole part. The authors of the present book thus entertain the hope that they may have succeeded not only in amplifying, clarifying, and fortifying the realistic critique, but also in exhibiting that critique as a basis for the solution of special philosophical problems, and for the pro- cedure of the special sciences. 1 The following introduction expresses opinions common to the several authors of this book; but it has proved convenient to make use of parts of the following articles which have already appeared in print. Montague. The New Realism and the Old. /. of Phil., Pyychol, etc., 1912, 9, 39. Perry. Realism as a Polemic and Program of Reform. J. of Phil., Pnychol., etc., 1910, 7, 337, 365. B X INTRODUCTION THE HISTORICAL SIGNIFICANCE OF THE NEW REALISM THE new realism is not an accident, nor a tour de force, nor an isolated and curious speculative eruption. Whatever may be thought of its correctness or power to endure, it must at least be accorded a place in the main current of modern thought. It is a fundamental and typical doctrine — definable in terms of the broad play of intellectual forces, and peculiarly characteristic of their present conjunction. The historical significance of the new realism appears most clearly in its relations with 'naive realism/ 'dualism' and 'sub- jectivism.' The new realism is primarily a doctrine concerning the relation between the knowing process and the thing known; and as such it is the latest phase of a movement of thought which has already passed through the three phases just indicated. Neo- realism, in other words, seeks to deal with the same problem that has given rise to 'naive realism,' 'dualism' and 'subjectivism'; and to profit by the errors as well as the discoveries for which these doctrines have been responsible. 1. The theory of naive realism is the most primitive of these theories. It conceives of objects as directly presented to con- sciousness and being precisely what they appear to be. Nothing intervenes between the knower and the world external to him. Objects are not represented in consciousness by ideas; they are themselves directly presented. This theory makes no distinction between seeming and being ; things are just what they seem. Con- sciousness is thought of as analogous to a light which shines out through the sense organs, illuminating the world outside the knower. There is in this naive view a complete disregard of the personal equation and of the elaborate mechanism underlying sense perception. In a world in which there was no such thing as error, this theory of the knowledge relation would remain unchal- lenged; but with the discovery of error and illusion comes per- HISTORICAL SIGNIFICANCE OF NEW REALISM 3 plexity. Dreams are perhaps the earliest phenomena of error to arouse the primitive mind from its dogmatic realism. How can a man lie asleep in his bed and at the same time travel to distant places and converse with those who are dead ? How can the events of the dream be reconciled with the events of waking experience ? The first method of dealing with this type of error is to divide the real world into two realms, equally objective and equally external, but the one visible, tangible, and regular, the other more or less invisible, mysterious, and capricious. The soul after death, and sometimes during sleep, can enter the second of these realms. The objectified dreamland of the child and the ghostland of the sav- age are the outcome of the first effort of natural realism to cope with the problem of error. It is easy to see, however, that this doubling up of the world of existing objects will only explain a very limited number of dream experiences, while to the errors of waking experience it is obviously inapplicable. Whenever, for example, the dream is concerned with the same events as those al- ready experienced in waking life, there can be no question of ap- pealing to a shadow world. Unreal events that are in conflict with the experience of one's fellows, and even with one's own more inclusive experience, must be banished completely from the ex- ternal world. Where, then, shall they be located ? What is more natural than to locate them inside the person who experiences them ? For it is only upon him that the unreal object produces any effect. The objects of our dreams and our fancies, and of illusions generally, are held to exist only 'in the mind.' They are like feelings and desires in being directly experienced only by a single mind. Thus the soul, already held to be the mysterious principle of life, and endowed with peculiar properties, transcending ordi- nary physical things, is further enriched by being made the habitat of the multitudinous hosts of non-existent objects. Still further reflection on the phenomena of error leads to the discovery of the element of relativity in all knowledge, and finally to the realiza- tion that no external happening can be perceived until after it has ceased to exist. The events we perceive as present are always 4 INTRODUCTION past, for in order to perceive anything it must send energy of some kind to our sense organs, and by the time the energy reaches us the phase of existence which gave rise to it has passed away. To this universal and necessary temporal aberration of perceived objects is added an almost equally universal spatial aberration. For all objects that move relatively to the observer are perceived not where they are when perceived, but, at best, where they were when the stimulus issued from them. And in addition to these spatial and temporal aberrations of perception we know that what we perceive will depend not only upon the nature of the object but on the nature of the medium through which its energies have passed on their way to our organism ; and also upon the condition of our sense organs and brain. Finally, we have every reason to believe that whenever the brain is stimulated in the same way in which it is normally stimulated by an object we shall experience that ob- ject even though it is in no sense existentially present. These many undeniable facts prove that error is no trivial and excep- tional phenomenon, but the normal, necessary, and universal taint from which every perceptual experience must suffer. 2. It is such considerations as these that have led to the aban- donment of naive realism in favor of dualism, the second of the aforementioned theories. According to this second theory, which is exemplified in the philosophies of Descartes and Locke, the mind never perceives anything external to itself. It can perceive only its own ideas or states. But as it seems impossible to account for the order in which these ideas occur by appealing to the mind in which they occur, it is held to be permissible and even necessary to infer a world of external objects resembling to a greater or less extent the effects, or ideas, which they produce in us. What we perceive is now held to be only a picture of what really exists. Consciousness is no longer thought of as analogous to a light which directly illumines the extra-organic world, but rather as a painter's canvas or a photographic plate on which objects in themselves imperceptible are represented. The great advantage of the second or picture theory is that it fully accounts for error and illusion; HISTORICAL SIGNIFICANCE OF NEW REALISM 5 the disadvantage of it is that it appears to account for nothing else. The only external world is one that we can never experience, the only world that we can have any experience of is the internal world of ideas. When we attempt to justify the situation by appealing to inference as the guarantee of this unexperienceable externality, we are met by the difficulty that the world we infer can only be made of the matter of experience, that is, can only be made up of mental pictures in new combinations. An inferred object is al- ways a perceptible object, one that could be in some sense experi- enced ; and, as we have seen, the only things that according to this view can be experienced are our mental states. Moreover, the world in which all our interests are centered is the world of experi- enced objects. Even if, per impossibile, we could justify the belief in a world beyond that which we could experience, it would be but a barren achievement, for such a world would contain none of the things that we see and feel. Such a so-called real world would be more alien to us and more thoroughly queer than were the ghost- land or dreamland which, as we remember, the primitive realist sought to use as a home for certain of the unrealities of life. 3. It seems very natural at such a juncture to try the experi- ment of leaving out this world of extra-mental objects, and con- tenting ourselves with a world in which there exist only minds and their states. This is the third theory, the theory of subjectivism. According to it, there can be no object without a subject, no exist- ence without a consciousness of it. To be, is to be perceived. The world of objects capable of existing independently of a knower (the belief in which united the natural realist and the dualistic realist) is now rejected. This third theory agrees with the first theory in being epistemologically monistic, that is, in holding to the presentative rather than to the representative theory of percep- tion ; for, according to the first theory, whatever is perceived must exist, and according to the present theory, whatever exists must be perceived. Naive realism subsumed the perceived as a species under the genus existent. Subjectivism subsumes the existent as a species under the genus perceived. But while the third theory 6 INTRODUCTION has these affiliations with the first theory, it agrees with the second theory in regarding all perceived objects as mental states — ideas inhering in the mind that knows them and as inseparable from that mind as any accident is from the substance that owns it. Subjectivism has many forms, or rather, many degrees. It oc- curs in its first and most conservative form in the philosophy of Berkeley. Descartes and Locke, and other upholders of the dualistic epistemology, had already gone beyond the requirements of the picture theory in respect to the secondary qualities of ob- jects. Not content with the doctrine that these qualities as they existed in objects could only be inferred, they had denied them even the inferential status which they accorded to primary qualities. The secondary qualities that we perceive are not even copies of what exists externally. They are the cloudy effects produced in the mind by combinations of primary qualities, and they resemble unreal objects in that they are merely subjective. The chief ground for this element of subjectivism in the systems of dualis- tic realism immediately preceding Berkeley, was the belief that relativity to the percipient implied subjectivity. As the secondary qualities showed this relativity, they were condemned as subjec- tive. Now it was the easiest thing in the world for Berkeley to show that an equal or even greater relativity pertained to the primary qualities. The perceived form, size, and solidity of an object depend quite as much upon the relation of the percipient to the object as do its color and temperature. If it be axiomatic that whatever is relative to the perceiver exists only as an idea, why, then, the primary qualities which were all that remained of the physical world could be reduced to mere ideas. But just here Berkeley brought his reasoning to an abrupt stop. He refused to recognize that (1) the relations between ideas or the order in which they are given to us, and (2) the other minds that are known, are quite as relative to the knower as are the primary and secondary qualities of the physical world. You can know other minds only in so far as you have experience of them, and to infer their independent existence involves just as much and just as little of the process of HISTORICAL SIGNIFICANCE OF NEW REALISM 7 objectifying and hypostatizing your own ideas as to infer the in- dependent existence of physical objects. Berkeley avoided this obvious result of his own logic by using the word 'notion' to describe the knowledge of those things that did not depend for their existence on the fact that they were known. If you had an idea of a thing — say of your neighbor's body — then that thing existed only as a mental state. But if you had a notion of a thing — say of your neighbor's mind — then that thing was quite ca- pable of existing independently of your knowing it. Considering the vigorous eloquence with which Berkeley inveighed against the tendency of philosophers to substitute words for thoughts, it is pathetic that he should himself have furnished such a striking example of that very fallacy. In later times Clifford and Pearson have not hesitated to avail themselves of a quite similar linguistic device for escaping the solipsistic conclusion of a consistent sub- jectivism. The distinction between the physical objects which as ' constructs ' exist only in the consciousness of the knower, and other minds which as 'ejects' can be known without being in any way dependent on the knower, is essentially the same both in its meaning and in its futility as the Berkeleian distinction of idea and notion. For the issue between realism and subjectivism does not arise from a psychocentric predicament — a difficulty of con- ceiving of objects apart from any consciousness — but rather from the much more radical 'ego-centric predicament,'1 the difficulty of conceiving known things to exist independently of my knowing them. And the poignancy of the predicament is quite independ- ent of the nature of the object itself, whether that be a physical thing such as my neighbor's body, or a psychical thing such as my neighbor's mind. Some part of this difficulty Hume saw and endeavored to meet in his proof that the spiritual substances of Berkeley were them- selves mere ideas; but Hume's position is itself subject to two criticisms : First, it succeeds no better than Berkeley's in avoid- ing a complete relativism or solipsism — for it is as difficult to ex- »Cf. below, 11-12. 8 INTRODUCTION plain how one 'bundle of perceptions' can have any knowledge of the other equally real 'bundle of perceptions' as to explain how one 'spirit' can have knowledge of other 'spirits.' Second, the Humean doctrine suffers from an additional difficulty peculiar to itself, in that by destroying the conception of the mind as a 'sub- stance,' it made meaningless the quite correlative conception of perceived objects as mental 'states.' If there is no substance there cannot be any states or accidents, and there ceases to be any sense in regarding the things that are known as dependent upon or inseparable from a knower. 4. Passing on to that form of subjectivism developed by Kant, we may note three points: (1) A step back toward dualism, in that he dallies with, even if he does not actually embrace, the dualistic notion of a ding-an-sich, a reality outside and beyond the realm of experienced objects which serves as their cause or ground. (2) A step in advance of the subjectivism of Berkeley and Hume, in that Kant reduces to the subjective status not merely the facts of nature but also her laws, so far, at least, as they are based upon the forms of space and time and upon the categories. (3) There appears in the Kantian system a wholly new feature which is des- tined to figure prominently in later systems. This is the dualistic conception of the knower, as himself a twofold being, tran- scendental and empirical. It is the transcendental or noumenal self that gives laws to nature, and that owns the experienced ob- jects as its states. The empirical or phenomenal self, on the other hand, is simply one object among others, and enjoys no special primacy in its relation to the world of which it is a part. The post-Kantian philosophies deal with the three points just mentioned in the following ways: (1) The retrograde feature of Kant's doctrine — the belief in the ding-an-sich — is abandoned. (2) The step in advance — the legislative power conferred by Kant upon the self as knower — is accepted and enlarged to the point of viewing consciousness as the source not only of the a priori forms of relation, but of all relations whatsoever. (3) The doctrine of the dual self is extended to the point of identifying in one absolute HISTORICAL SIGNIFICANCE OF NEW REALISM 9 self the plurality of transcendental selves held to by Kant, with the result that our various empirical selves and the objects of their experience are all regarded as the manifestations or fragments of a single, perfect, all-inclusive, and eternal self. But it is not hard to see that this new dualism of the finite and the absolute selves involves the same difficulties as those which we found in the Cartesian dualism of conscious state and physical object. For either the experience of the fragment embraces the experiences of the absolute or it does not. If the former, then the absolute be- comes knowable, to be sure, but only at the cost of losing its ab- soluteness and being reduced to a mere 'state ' of the alleged frag- ment. The existence of the absolute will then depend upon the fact that it is known by its own fragments, and each fragmentary self will have to assume that its own experience constitutes the entire universe — which is solipsism. If the other horn of the dilemma be chosen and the independent reality of the absolute be insisted upon, then it is at the cost of making the absolute unknow- able, of reducing it to the status of the unexperienceable external world of the dualistic realist. The dilemma itself is the inevitable consequence of making knowledge an internal relation and hence constitutive of its objects. Indeed, a large part of the philosophi- cal discussion of recent years has been concerned with the endeavor of the absolutists to defend their doctrine from the attacks of empiricists of the Berkeleian and Humean tradition in such a way as to avoid equally the Scylla of epistemological dualism and the Charybdis of, solipsism. But, as we have seen, the more empirical subjectivists of the older and strictly British school are open to the same criticism as that which they urge upon the absolutists; for it is as difficult for the Berkeleian to justify his belief hi the existence of other spirits, or the phenomenalistic follower of Hume his belief in bundles or streams of experience other than his own, as for the absolutist to justify those features [of the absolute experience which lie beyond the experience of the finite frag- ments. 5. And now enter upon this troubled scene the new realists, 10 INTRODUCTION offering to absolutists and phenomenalists impartially their new theory of the relation of knower to known. From the standpoint of this new theory all subjectivists suffer from a common complaint. The ontological differences that separate such writers as Fichte and Berkeley, Mr. Bradley and Professor Karl Pearson, are, for a realist, overshadowed by the epistemological error that unites them. The escape from subjec- tivism and the formulation of an alternative that shall be both reme- dial and positively fruitful, constitutes the central preeminent issue for any realistic protagonist. It is prior to all other philosophical issues, such as monism and pluralism, eternalism and temporalism, materialism and spiritualism, or even pragmatism and intellec- tualism. This does not mean that the new realism shall not lead to a solution of these problems, but only that as a basis for their clear discussion it is first of all essential to get rid of subjec- tivism. The new realists' relational theory is in essentials very old. To understand its meaning it is necessary to go back beyond Kant, beyond Berkeley, beyond even Locke and Descartes — far back to that primordial common sense which believes in a world that exists independently of the knowing of it, but believes also that that same independent world can be directly presented in con- sciousness and not merely represented or copied by 'ideas.' In short, the new realism is, broadly speaking, a return to that naive or natural realism which was the first of our three typical theories of the knowledge relation ; and as such, it should be sharply dis- tinguished from the dualistic or inferential realism of the Car- tesians. But the cause of the abandonment of naive realism in favor of the dualistic or picture theory was the apparently hope- less disagreement of the world as presented in immediate experi- ence with the true or corrected system of objects in whose reality we believe. So the first and most urgent problem for the new realists is to amend the realism of common sense in such wise as to make it compatible with the facts of relativity. For this reason especial attention has been given in the present THE REALISTIC POLEMIC 11 volume 1 to a discussion of those special phenomena, such as illu- sion and error, which are supposed to discredit natural realism, and set going a train of thought that cannot be stopped short of subjectivism. It is necessary to inquire closely into the mechan- ism of perception, and into the logic of contradiction and falsity. And it is necessary to obtain a definition of the central thesis of realism, the thesis of independence, that shall not be so loose as to violate the facts, nor so vague and formal as to disregard them.2 II THE REALISTIC POLEMIC INASMUCH as subjectivism, renewed and fortified under the name of 'idealism/ is the dominant philosophy of the day, it affords the chief resistance which an innovating philosophy such as realism has to overcome. The realistic polemic is therefore primarily a polemic against subjectivism; but the errors of which realism finds subjectivistic philosophies to be guilty, are not necessarily confined to such philosophies. They may be generalized; and in so far as they are generalized their discovery is of greater mo- ment. The following are some of the traditional errors which neo-realism has thus far succeeded in generalizing. 1. The fallacy of argument from the ego-centric predicament. — The 'ego-centric predicament' consists in the impossibility of finding anything that is not known.3 This is a predicament rather than a discovery, because it refers to a difficulty of procedure, rather than to a character of things. It is impossible to eliminate the knower without interrupting observation ; hence the peculiar difficulty of discovering what characters, if any, things possess when not known. When this situation is formulated as a proposi- tion concerning things, the result is either the redundant inference that all known things are known, or the false inference that all 1 Cf. below, Nos. IV, V, VI. * Cf. below, No. II. 1 In this connection, ' known ' means ' given as an object of thought.' 12 INTRODUCTION things are known. The former is, on account of its redundancy, not a proposition at all; and its use results only in confusing it with the second proposition, which involves a petitio principii. The falsity of the inference, in the case of the latter proposition, lies in its being a use of the method of agreement unsupported by the method of difference. It is impossible to argue from the fact that everything one finds is known, to the conclusion that knowing is a universal condition of being, because it is impossible to find non-things which are not known. The use of the method of agree- ment without negative cases is a fallacy. It should be added that at best the method of agreement is a preliminary aid to exact thought, and can throw no light whatsoever on what can be meant by saying that knowing is a condition of being. Yet this method, misapplied, is the main proof, perhaps the only proof, that has been offered of the cardinal principle of idealistic philosophies — the definition of being in terms of consciousness. It is difficult, on account of their very lack of logical form, to obtain pure cases of philosophical fallacies. Then, too, this particular fallacy has so far become a commonplace as to be regarded as a self-evident truth. The step in which it is employed is omitted or obscured in many idealistic treatises. In others it is spread so thin, is so pervasive and insidious, that while it lends whatever support is offered for the cardinal idealistic principle, it is nowhere explicitly formulated. But the following will serve as a typical illustration. "Things exist," says Renouvier, "and all things have a common character, that of being represented, of appearing ; for if there were no repre- sentation of things, how should I speak of them?" 1 It is clear that no more is proved by this argument than that things must be 'represented' if one is to 'speak of them.' That all things have the common character of being 'spoken of,' which is the funda- mental thesis restated in a new form, is left without any proof whatsoever. 2. The fallacy of pseudo-simplicity. — There is a disposition in philosophy as well as in common sense to assume the simplicity 1 Renouvier. Mind, 1877, 2, 378. THE REALISTIC POLEMIC 13 of that which is only familiar or stereotyped. This error has conspired with the error just examined to lend a certain plausi- bility to subjectivism. For one would scarcely assert with so much gravity that the world was his idea, or that the 'I think* must accompany every judgment, unless he supposed that the first personal pronoun referred to something that did not require further elucidation. Self-consciousness could never have figured in idealistic philosophies as the immediate and primary certainty if it were understood to be a complex and problematic conception. Yet such it must be admitted to be, once its practical sim- plicity, based on habits of thought and speech, is discounted. Similarly the common dogma, to the effect that consciousness can be known only irrespectively, is based on the assumption that it is known introspectively, and that thus approached it is a simple datum. Traditional spiritistic conceptions of will, activity, im- mediacy, and life, rest on the same fundamental misapprehension as does the materialistic acceptance of body as an irreducible en- tity. Thus what is really at stake here is nothing less than the method of analysis itself. In exact procedure it is not permitted to assert the simplicity of any concept until after analysis. That the concepts enumerated above are not analytically simple, is proved by the fact that when they are treated as simple, it is necessary to give them a complex existence also in order to account for what is known about them. It is customary to say that this is a 'manifestation' or 'transformation' of the simple and more fundamental reality; but this is to reverse the order which is proper to thought as the deliberate and systematic attempt to know. It is equivalent to asserting that the more pains we take to know, the less real is the object of our knowledge ; a proposition which is never asserted without being contradicted, since it ex- presses the final critical analysis of the thinker who asserts it. The following is a characteristic example of the error of 'pseudo-sim- plicity,' as applied to the conception of activity. "Every man," says Professor Ward, "knows the difference be- tween feeling and doing, between idle reverie and intense thought, 14 INTRODUCTION between impotent and aimless drifting and unswerving tenacity of purpose, being the slave of every passion or the master of him- self. ... It must surely ever remain futile, nay, even foolish, to attempt to explain either receptivity or activity; for what is there in experience more fundamental? And being thus funda- mental, the prime staple of all experience, it is absurd to seek to prove them real, since in the first and foremost sense of reality the real and they are one." 1 Nevertheless, activity and passivity are capable of being analyzed in a variety of ways, logical, physical, and psychological ; 2 and their nature can be regarded as a simple datum only in so far as such analysis is deliberately avoided. They are simples only in so far as they are not yet analyzed, 3. The fallacy of exclusive particularity. — It is ordinarily as- sumed that a particular term of any system belongs to such system exclusively. That this is a false assumption is proved empirically. The point 6 of the class of points that constitutes the straight line abc may belong also to the class of points that constitutes the inter- secting straight line xby. The man John Doe who belongs to the class Republican Party may belong also to the intersecting class captains of industry. Unless this multiple classification of terms were possible, discourse would break down utterly. All the terms of discourse are general in the sense that they belong to several contexts. It is this fact that accounts for the origin and the usefulness of language. Without this generality of terms the world would possess no structure, not even motion or similarity; for there could be no motion if the same could not be in different places at different times, and there could be no similarity if the same could not appear in different qualitative groupings. It is little wonder, then, that the virtual rejection of this principle by philosophy has led to a fundamental and perpetual difficulty. To this error may perhaps be traced the untenability of Platonic universalism, recognized apparently by Plato himself, and the 1 Ward, J. Naturalism and Agnosticism, 2, 52, 53. » Cf. e.g. James, W. The Experience of Activity, in Essays in Radical Em- piricism, VI. THE REALISTIC POLEMIC 15 untenability of modern particularism, attested by the desperate efforts which almost every modern philosopher has made to save himself from it. The most familiar variety of particularism is found in naturalism. This may be traced to the naive bias for the space-time order, or that historical series of bodily changes which constitutes the course of nature. Naturalism asserts that this is the only system, and that its terms, the several bodily events, belong to it exclusively. That this theory is untenable is evident at once, since in order that bodily events shall possess the structure and connections necessary to them, being must contain other terms, such as places, times, numbers, etc., that are not bodily events. But historically, naturalism has been discredited mainly by its failure to provide for the system of ideas, a system without which the bodily system itself could not be known ; and it is the exclusive particularity of the terms of this latter that has figured most prominently in philosophical discussions. In dualism of the Cartesian type the terms of nature and the terms of knowledge are regarded as exclusive, but in order that knowledge shall mean anything at all, it is assumed that there is some sort of representative relation between them. Spinoza and Leibniz endeavored to bring them together through a third and neutral term. Among the English philosophers the impossibility of showing how the mind can know nature if each mind is a closed circle, possessing its content wholly within itself, leads finally to the abolition of nature as an independent system. Thus the pen- dulum swings from naturalism to subjectivism; and in the whole course of this dialectic the mistaken principle of exclusive par- ticularity is assumed. 4. The fallacy of definition by initial predication. — This form of error is a natural sequel to the last. A subject of discourse is viewed initially under one of its aspects, or is taken initially as a term in some specific complex or relational manifold. Then, owing to the error of exclusive particularity, it is assumed that this sub- ject of discourse can have no other aspect, or belong to no other 16 INTRODUCTION relational manifold. Thus the initial characterization becomes definitive and final. Subjectivism, again, affords the most notable instances of the error. Any subject of discourse may be construed as such; that is, as a thing talked about or 'taken account of,' as an object of experience or knowledge. The vogue of the psychological, in- trospective, or reflective method in modern thought has given rise to the custom of construing things first according to their place in the context of consciousness. Similarly, the habit of self-con- sciousness among philosophers has emphasized the relation of things to self; and the prominence of epistemology in modern philosophy has tended to an initial characterization of things ac- cording to their places in the process of knowledge, just as the prominence of religious issues led early Christian ascetics to name things first after their part in the drama of the soul's salvation. Thus, idealism, quite unconscious of having prejudged the main question from the outset, "seeks to interpret the universe after the analogy of conscious life, and regards experience as for us the great reality."1 Or, as another writer expressed it, "we must start . . . from the whole of experience as such." 2 But all such initial characterizations must be regarded as accidental. Allow- ance must be duly made for alternative and complementary char- acterizations; and the question of the priority of the characteri- zation to which any subject of discourse submits must be discussed quite independently of the order which is determined by habit or bias. In short, the very general disposition at the present time to begin with a psychological or epistemological version of things must not be allowed in the least to prejudice the question as to whether that version is definitive or important. 5. The speculative dogma. — By the 'speculative dogma' is meant the assumption for philosophical purposes that there is an all-sufficient, all-general principle, a single fundamental propo- 1 Lindsay, J. Studies in European Philosophy, 207. * Baillie, J. B. Idealistic Construction of Experience, 105. THE REALISTIC POLEMIC 17 sition that adequately determines or explains everything. This assumption has commonly taken one or the other of two forms. By many it has been assumed that such a principle constitutes the proper content or subject matter of philosophy. Thus Plato said: "And when I speak of the other division of the intelligible you will understand me to speak of that other sort of knowledge which reason herself attains by the power of dialectic, using the hypotheses not as first principles, but only as hypotheses — that is to say, as steps and points of departure into a region which is above hypotheses, in order that she may soar beyond them to the first principle of the whole ; and clinging to this and then to that which depends on this, by successive steps she descends again without the aid of any sensible object, beginning and ending in ideas." l And Caird makes the same assumption when he says that "Philosophy professes to seek and to find the principle of unity which underlies all the manifold particular truths of the separate sciences." 2 But such an assumption is dogmatic, because it ignores the prior ques- tion as to whether there is such a principle or not. So far as the general task of philosophy is concerned, this must be treated as an open question. Philosophy does aim, it is true, to generalize as widely and comprehend as adequately as possible; but a loosely aggregated world, abounding in unmitigated variety, is a philo- sophical hypothesis. The discovery of a highly coherent system under which all the wealth of experience could be subsumed would be the most magnificent of philosophical achievements; but if there is no such system, philosophy must be satisfied with some- thing less — with whatever, in fact, there happens to be. By others, in the second place, it has been assumed that the idea of such a principle or system is the property of every thoughtful per- son, the existence of an object corresponding to it being alone doubtful. This assumption gave rise to the ontological proof of God, which carried conviction only so long as man did not question the definiteness and meaning of the idea; for the assumption 1 Plato, (Jowett, trans.) Republic, 511, B. * Caird, E. The Social Philosophy and Religion of Comte, xiii. 0 18 INTRODUCTION obscured a problem, the problem, namely, as to whether there is any idea corresponding to the words ens realissimum. The pos- sibility of defining, on general logical grounds, a maximum of being or truth, is, to say the least, highly questionable; and it is cer- tain that this problem must properly precede any inferences from such a maximal idea. The speculative dogma has been the most prolific cause of the verbal abuses which abound in philosophy, and which are to be considered separately. It is through this dogma that various words have been invested with a certain hyperbole and equivo- cation, in consequence of the attempt to stretch their meaning to fit the speculative demand. A further evil arising from the speculative dogma is the unjust and confusing disparagement of positive knowledge through invidious comparison with this Un- known God to which the philosopher has erected his altar. 6. The error of verbal suggestion. — Words which do not possess a clear and unambiguous meaning, but which nevertheless have a rhetorical effect owing to their associations, lend themselves to a specious discourse, having no cognitive value in itself, and stand- ing in the way of the attainment of genuine knowledge. This is Bacon's famous idol of the forum. In philosophy this reliance on the suggestive, rather than the proper denotative or connotative function of words, is due not only to man's general and ineradicable tendency to verbalism, but also to the wide vogue of doctrines that are fundamentally inarticulate. We have already examined two errors which lead philosophers to accept such doctrines. The error of pseudo-simplicity involves a reference to topics that cannot be analytically expressed; they cannot be identified and assigned an unequivocal name. The speculative dogma has, as we have seen, led to the use of words which shall somehow convey a sense of finality, or of limitless and exhaustive application, where no specific object or exact concept possessing such characters is offered for inspection. This is what Berkeley calls the "method of growing in expression, and dwindling in notion." Ordinarily the words so used have a precise meaning also, and there results a THE REALISTIC POLEMIC 19 double evil. On the one hand, the exact meaning of such terms as 'force,' 'matter,' 'consciousness,' 'will/ etc., is blurred and vitiated; and on the other hand, their speculative meaning borrows a content to which it is not entitled. The desire of philos- ophers to satisfy the religious demand for an object of worship or faith, doubtless one of the fundamental motives of the speculative dogma, leads to yet another variety of verbal suggestion, in which a technical philosophical conception is given a name that possesses eloquence and power of edification. Thus philosophers commonly prefer the term 'eternal' to the term 'non-temporal,' and 'in- finite' to 'series with no last term,' or 'class, a part of which can be put in one-to-one correspondence with the whole.' Such terms as ' significance,' ' supreme,' ' highest,' ' unity,' have a similar value. Or the same end may be achieved by decorating almost any word with a capital letter, as is exemplified by the emotional difference between truth and Truth, or absolute and Absolute. Finally, there is a verbal abuse which is worse, even, than equivocation; for it is possible to invent utterly fictitious con- cepts simply by combining words. In such cases, the constituent concepts, if the words happen to signify any, are not united. They may be positively repugnant, or simply irrelevant. At any rate, they have not been tested for consistency, and whether they do or do not constitute a true system or complex concept remains wholly problematic. Such, for example, is the case with Eucken's "total activity, which by its own movement develops into an independent reality and at the same time comprehends the opposition of subject and object, subjectivity and objectivity. " * Such procedure is the principal source of the fallacy of obscurum per obscurius and affords an almost unlimited opportunity for error. 7. The fallacy of illicit importance. — This is one of the most insidious errors which has ever been foisted upon mankind, and it is the idealist who has popularized it. It consists in inferring that, because a proposition is self-evident or unchallengeable, there- 1 Eucken. (Pogson, trans.) Life of the Spirit, 329. 20 INTRODUCTION fore it is important. There is a healthy animal instinct behind the fallacy. Men have early learned that the certain affords, on the whole, a safer basis for conduct than the uncertain. The merchant who is sure of his market grows rich faster than his igno- rant competitor. The statesman who is sure of his constituents acts with directness and decision. So it is throughout all practi- cal life. Now, the practical man never reflects upon his own men- tal processes, and thus he fails to note that the certainty he feels toward things is not an attribute of them, but only a certain pre- cision in his attitude toward them. But the fact that the relations are unequivocal and clear is no proof that they happen to be of much significance. A may surely be C, and yet its being C may be the most trivial circumstance. A man, for instance, may be abso- lutely sure he likes cucumbers; but this does not prove that cucumbers are the true foundation of dietetics, nor that his liking of them reveals either his own nature or the nature of cucumbers. Undeterred by such obvious cases, however, the idealist is wont to reason that all philosophy and all science must be built upon the one fact that nobody can make any unchallengeable as- sertion about anything except his having an immediate experience. One might ask the idealist whether he is any more certain of being aware than he is of the presented object ; whether, for ex- ample, in addition to saying: "I am certain that I am experi- encing" — he cannot say with equal assurance : "There certainly is a tree of some sort over yonder." But to take up this debate is to pass beyond the fallacy which he has committed. And no so- lution of the question alters the fact that he has erred logically hi holding that, because A is undeniably B, therefore B is an impor- tant characteristic of A. There is no sure connection between the axiomatic and the significant. To think there is, is vicious in- tellectualism. The fallacy is curable only by the use of strict logic, but by this very easily. If one person is certain that a dis- tant object is a tree, while his companion is equally certain that the same object is an automobile, is it not obvious that certainty THE REALISTIC PROGRAM OF REFORM 21 is a negligible factor in the problem of deciding what the object really is? Ill THE REALISTIC PROGRAM OF REFORM PHILOSOPHY has repeatedly thrown off its bad habits, and aroused itself to critical vigilance. Furthermore, there is good ground for asserting that there has never before been so great an opportunity of reform. Logic and mathematics, the tradi- tional models of procedure, are themselves being submitted to a searching revision that has already thrown a new light on the gen- eral principles of exact thinking; and there is promise of more light to come, for science has for all time become reflectively conscious of its own method. The era of quarrelsome misun- derstanding between criticism and positive knowledge is giving way to an era of united and complementary endeavor. It must not be forgotten that philosophy is peculiarly dependent on logic. Natural science in its empirical and experimental phases can safely be guided by instinct, because it operates in the field of objects defined by common sense. But the very objects of philosophy are the fruit of analysis. Its task is the correction of the cate- gories of common sense, and all hope of a profitable and valid re- sult must be based on an expert critical judgment. The present situation, then, affords philosophy an opportunity of adopting a more rigorous procedure and assuming a more systematic form. It is with reference to this opportunity that it is worth while here to repeat the advice which is our common inheritance from the great philosophical reformers. None of these canons is origi- nal, but all are pertinent and timely. 1. The scrupulous use of words. — This is a moral rather than a logical canon. There is need in philosophy of a greater fastidi- ousness and nicety in the use of words. A regard for words is, in philosophy, the surest proof of a sensitive scientific conscience ; for words are the instruments of philosophical procedure, and 22 INTRODUCTION deserve the same care as the lancet of the surgeon or the balance of the chemist. A complacent and superior disregard of words is as fatuous as it is offensive. It is a healthier intellectual symptom to feel as Maclan felt in Chesterton's 'Ball and the Cross.' "Why shouldn't we quarrel about a word? What is the good of words if they aren't important enough to quarrel over ? Why do we choose one word more than another if there isn't any difference between them ? If you called a woman a chimpanzee instead of an angel, wouldn't there be a quarrel about a word? If you're not going to argue about words, what are you going to argue about ? Are you going to convey your meaning to me by moving your ears ? The church and the heresies always used to fight about words, because they are the only things worth fighting about." l 2. Definition. — "The light of human minds," says Hobbes, "is perspicuous words, but by exact definitions first snuffed and purged from all ambiguities." Words are properly signs. They are serviceable in proportion as they are self-effacing. A skillful word will introduce the hearer or reader to his object, and then retire ; only the awkward word will call attention to itself. It fol- lows, then, that the only means of escaping quarrels about words is to use words with discrimination, with careful reference to their objective purport, or usefulness as means of access to ideas. Fur- thermore, a word is essentially a social instrument, whether used for record or communication, and requires that its relation to an object or idea shall be agreed on and conventionalized. This is the only means of bringing several minds together in a common topic of discourse. "Syllables," says John Toland, "though never so well put together, if they have not ideas fix'd to them, are but words spoken in the air, and cannot be the ground of a reasonable service." 2 Philosophy is peculiarly dependent upon a clear definition of the reference of words because, as we have already seen, its objects are not those of common sense. It cannot rely on the ordinary 1 Chesterton. The Ball and the Cross, 96. 1 Toland. Christianity not Mysterious (2d ed.) , 30. THE REALISTIC PROGRAM OF REFORM 23 denotation of words. This fact affords a perennial and abundant source of confusion, from which there is no escape save through the creation of a technical vocabulary. Bacon's observations on this matter are worthy of being quoted in full. "Now words," he says, "being commonly framed and applied according to the capacity of the vulgar, follow those lines of division which are most obvious to the vulgar understanding. And whenever an under- standing of greater acuteness or a more diligent observation would alter those lines to suit the true divisions of nature, words stand in the way and resist the change. Whence it comes to pass that the high and formal discussions of learned men end oftentimes in disputes about words and names, with which (according to the use and wisdom of the mathematicians) it would be more prudent to begin, and so by means of definitions reduce them to order. " l Definition, then, means, in the first instance, the unequivocal and conventional reference of words. But there is a further ques- tion which arises from the use of single words to refer to complex objects. If such a reference is to be unequivocal, it is necessary that there should be a verbal complex mediating between the single word and the complex object. Thus if a circle is defined as 'the class of points equidistant from a given point,' this means that a circle is a complex object whose components are specified by the words in the given phrase. The single word is virtually an abbre- viation of the phrase. The clarity of words depends in the end on their possessing a conventional reference to simple objects. But with the progress of analysis and the demonstration of the unsuspected or unexplored complexity of things, the single word which at first denoted the object in its pre-analytical simplicity, comes to stand for several words which denote the components of the object in their post-analytical simplicity. Definition, then, means two things : first, a convention regarding the substitution of a single word for a group of words ; second, a convention re- garding the reference of words to objects.2 1 Bacon. Novum Organum (edition of Ellis and Spedding), IV, 61. 2 The definition of things, rather than words, is apparently the same as knowledge in general. 24 INTRODUCTION 3. Analysis. — The term 'analysis' properly refers not to the special method of any branch of knowledge, but to the method of exact knowledge in general, to that method of procedure in which the problematic is discovered to be a complex of simples. Such procedure may lead to the discovery of fine identities in the place of gross differences, or fine differences in the place of gross identities. Analysis in this sense means only the careful, sys- tematic, and exhaustive examination of any topic of discourse. It cannot, then, be proper to assert that such procedure destroys its object. It does, it is true, require that naivete" and innocence of mind shall give place to sophistication ; or that ignorance shall give place to some degree of explicitly formulated knowledge. But even the discovery that such psychological or moral values are lost is itself the result of analysis. Nor is there any difficulty in providing a place for such values within the psychological or moral systems to which they belong. In the second place, it cannot be proper to assert that there is anything which necessarily escapes analysis, such as 'real' change or 'real' activity. The method of analysis does not require that change and activity shall be any- thing other than what any investigation shall discover them to be. Analysis may show either that they are unanalyzable or that they may be further reduced. If they turn out to be unanalyzable, it can only be because they exhibit no complexity of structure, no plurality of necessary factors. If they turn out to be reducible, then they must be identical with the totality of their components. If they appear to differ from such a totality, then they must appear so to differ in some respect, and this respect must at once be added to complete the totality. It is especially important not to forget the combining relations. A toy is not identical with the collection of the fragments into which it has been shattered, but it is identi- cal with these fragments in that particular arrangement which has been destroyed. Similarly dynamics does not reduce motion to the occupancy of positions, but to the occupancy of positions in a temporal order. There is a perfectly clear difference between geometry or statics, on the one hand, and dynamics on the other. THE REALISTIC PROGRAM OF REFORM 23 It is important also not to confuse analysis and synthesis with the physical operation that often accompanies them. For the pur- poses of knowledge it is not necessary to put Humpty Dumpty together again, but only to recognize that Humpty Dumpty is not himself unless the pieces are together. The common prejudice against analysis is due in part to this false supposition that it is an attempt to substitute a collection of parts for an arrangement of parts. But it is due also to a more or less habitual confusion between things and words. Those who have employed the analytical method have been by no means guiltless in the matter. So soon as any word obtains currency it begins to pose as a thing in its own right, and discourse is con- stantly tending to take on the form of a logomachy. It has not unnaturally been supposed that analysts intended to verbalize reality, to give to its parts the artificial and stereotyped character of words, and to its processes the formal arrangement of grammar. But, as we have already seen, verbalism cannot be avoided by a deliberate carelessness in the use of words. If words are to be both useful and subordinate, it is necessary that they should be kept in working order, like signposts kept up to date, with their inscriptions legible and their pointing true. 4. Regard for logical form. — Logic is at the present time in a state of extraordinary activity, and able both to stimulate and to enrich philosophy. The principal contribution which modern logic is prepared to make to philosophy concerns the form of exact knowledge. This problem is by no means wholly solved, and there is an important work to be done which only philosophers can do. But the mathematical logicians have already broken and fer- tilized the ground. The theory of relations, the theory of ' logical constants' or indefinables, the theory of infinity and continuity, and the theory of classes and systems, concern everything fun- damental in philosophy. No philosopher can ignore these and like theories without playing the part of an amateur. The mathe- matical logicians may be quite mistaken, or they may have failed to go to the root of things ; but in that case they must be over- 26 INTRODUCTION taken in their error and corrected on their own grounds, if the field of scientific philosophy is not to be abandoned to them altogether. The present situation is certainly intolerable ; for philosophy deals with the same topics as modern logic, but treats popularly and confusedly what modern logic treats with the painstaking thoroughness and exactness of the expert. There is another respect in which modern logic should be of service to philosophy. In the course of a reconstruction of the foundations of mathematics, certain general canons of good think- ing have come to light ; and these are directly applicable to philo- sophical procedure.1 We refer to such canons as 'consistency' and 'simplicity.' These canons are new in the sense that they are now well enough defined to afford a means of testing any theory. A theory is consistent when its fundamental propositions actually generate terms, or when a class can be found which they define ; and a theory satisfies the criterion of simplicity or parsimony when none of its fundamental propositions can be deduced from the rest. It behooves philosophy, then, both to ally itself with logic, in the investigation of the most ultimate concepts, such as relation, class, system, order, indefinable, etc., and also to apply to its own constructive procedure the most refined tests of scientific form. It is one of the major purposes of the new realism to justify and to extend the method of logic and of exact science in general. For this reason one of the essays in this volume 2 is especially devoted to defending the truthfulness of that method and giving it full ontological validity. 5. Division of the question. — Although philosophy is especially charged with correcting the results obtained in each special in- vestigation by results obtained from other investigations, it is folly to ignore the necessity, humanly speaking, of dealing with one problem at a time. Not only is the attempt to raise and answer all questions together futile, but it prevents either definite- ness of concepts or cogency of reasoning. Exact knowledge must 1 Cf. Schmidt. Critique of Cognition and its Principles, J. of Phil., Psychol., etc., 1909, 6, 281. » No. III. THE REALISTIC PROGRAM OF REFORM 27 be precisely limited in its application. A disposition in philosophy to employ terms in an unlimited sense, and to make unlimited assertions, is the principal reason why philosophy at the pres- ent time possesses no common body of theory. And for the same reason philosophy is to-day without any common plan of work to be done. English and American philosophers have been much exer- cised during the past decade over what is called 'the problem of truth.' It is assumed that the various parties to this discussion are referring to the same thing; but it is doubtful if this would e-rer be suspected, did they not specifically mention one another's •lames and writings. These quarrels are perhaps due less to dis- agreement on the merits of any question, than to an irritable de- termination to be heard. If a sober and patient attempt were made to reduce the present differences of philosophical opinion to debatable propositions, the first result would be a division of the question at issue. It would certainly appear that the present- day problem of truth is one problem only so long as it is a symbol of factional dispute ; discuss it, and it at once proves to be many problems, as independent of one another as any problems can be. If one undertakes to enumerate these problems, one readily finds as many as seven : (1) The problem of non-existence : What dis- position is to be made of negated propositions, of non-temporal propositions, and of imaginary propositions? (2) The problem of the one and the many : How may many elements belong to one system ? (3) The problem of logical form : What are the ultimate categories? (4) The problem of methodology: How shall one best proceed in order to know ? (5) The problem of universality : How can that which is known at a moment transcend that mo- ment ? (6) The problem of the values of knowledge : What are the criteria of right believing? (7) The problem of the relation between belief and its object : In what respect does belief directly or indirectly modify its object? If agreement, or even intelligent disagreement, is to be obtained, philosophical issues must be sharpened. If any steady advance is to be made, special problems must be examined in order, and one 28 INTRODUCTION at a time. There is a large group of such special problems that is by general consent assigned to philosophy. In addition to those already enumerated, there are such problems as consciousness, causality, matter, particularity and generality, individuality, teleology, all of them problems whose solution is of the first im- portance both for the special sciences and for religious belief. These problems are examined by the traditional philosophy ; but they are not sufficiently isolated, nor examined with sufficient intensive application. They find their place in most philosophical treatises as applications of a general system, and not as problems to be examined independently on their merits. 6. Explicit agreement. — The recent discussion of the desir- ability and expediency of a 'philosophical platform' has developed a difference of opinion as to whether agreement should be explicit or implicit.1 Agreement of some sort is conceded to be a desidera- tum, but there are some who believe that a common tradition or historical background is all that is necessary. Now is it not evi- dent that in theoretical or scientific procedure there is no agree- ment until it is explicitly formulated ? The philosophical classics afford no basis for agreement, because they are open to interpre- tation. The difficulty is merely complicated through the necessity of first agreeing on the meaning of a text. To employ terms and propositions in their historical sense is to adopt precisely the course which is adopted by common sense. It means the introduction into what is supposed to be exact discourse of the indeterminate human values with which tradition is incrusted. In exact dis- course the meaning of every term must be reviewed ; no stone can be allowed to go into the building that has not been inspected and approved by the builder. Otherwise the individual philosopher is no more than an instrument in the hands of the welt-geist. He must be possessed by a fatalistic confidence that the truth will take care of itself if he only repeats the formulas that he has learned in the schools or in the market place. But the most precious and 1 Cf. Schmidt, Creighton, and Leighton, /. of Phil., Psychol., etc., 1909, 6, 141, 240, 519, 673. THE REALISTIC PROGRAM OF REFORM 29 cherished privilege of philosophy is the critical independence of each generation. Every philosophical reformer from the begin- ning of European thought has been moved by a distrust of tradi- tion, and has proclaimed the need of a perpetual watchful- ness lest the prestige of opinion be mistaken for the weight of evidence. If agreement is to be based on tradition, then tradition, with all its ambiguity, its admixture of irrelevant associations, and its un- lawful authority, is made the arbiter of philosophical disputes. That no theoretical difference is ever really judged in this way is abundantly proved from the present situation in philosophy. We sympathize, but we do not agree ; we differ, but we do not disagree. It is of more importance in theoretical procedure that two or three should agree, than that all should sympathize. "If the trumpet gives an uncertain sound," says Toland, "who shall prepare him- self to the battle?" Agreement and disagreement alike require the explicit formulation of theories in terms freshly defined. It is not to be supposed that those who insist on the necessity of explicit agreement have in mind any general unanimity. The principle would be satisfied if a single philosopher could be found to agree with himself — provided the agreement were explicit. For then it would be possible for others to disagree with him, and to disagree explicitly. We should then have before us a number of carefully formulated propositions, which could be tested and de- bated in the light of the evidence, propositions which would be the common property of philosophers and the material with which to construct an impersonal system of philosophical knowledge. The first duty of philosophers, then, is not to agree, but to make their implicit agreements or disagreements explicit. Moreover it is not easy to see how this duty can be escaped without entirely abandoning philosophy's claim to be a theoretical discipline. If we cannot express our meaning in exact terms, in terms that we are willing should stand as final, if like the sophists of old we must make long speeches and employ the arts of rhetoric ; then let us at least cultivate literature. At present we are bad scientists and 30 INTRODUCTION worse poets. But philosophy is not necessarily ineffable.1 The dif- ficulties which some philosophies have in meeting the demands of exact discourse are gratuitous, and are due to a habit of mixing theory, on the one hand, with the history of theory, and, on the other hand, with common belief. It is not necessary that phi- losophy should abandon its interest in either history or common belief, but it is necessary that it should isolate those interests, and not permit them to compromise its direct study of problems. 7. The separation of philosophical research from the study of the history of philosophy. — A problem can be solved only by the attentive examination of that which the problem denotes. But a problem of historical exegesis, and an original philosophical prob- lem, necessarily denote different things and direct the attention to different quarters. Thus the problem of Hume's conception of causality directs attention to a text, whereas the problem of causal- ity directs attention to types of sequence or dependence exhibited in nature. It is worth while to formulate this commonplace be- cause there is a present-day habit of procedure that obscures it. It is customary to assume that it is the mark of rigorous scholar- ship in philosophy to confine oneself to commentaries on the classics. To raise the question of the importance of the history of philosophy is not necessary. That it has an indispensable place in human culture and in the discipline of every philosopher is not to be doubted ; but that it has a higher dignity than a direct and independent analysis of special problems seems to be nothing more than a superstition. What dignity the history of philosophy pos- sesses it derives from the originality of the individual philosophers whose achievements it records. If philosophy were to consist in the study of the history of philosophy, it would have no history. Doubtless the by-product of originality is charlatanry and sopho- moric conceit ; but mankind is not less well served by this than by the complacent pedantry which is the by-product of erudition. But whether the historical form of treatment does or does not »Cf. Sheffer, H. M. Ineffable Philosophies, /. of Phil, Psychol., etc., 1909, 6, 123. REALISM AS A CONSTRUCTIVE PHILOSOPHY 31 lend dignity to philosophical discourse, it certainly adds com- plexity and difficulty. Ferrier, good Hegelian though he was at heart, confided to his readers the hopelessness of undertaking to show whether his conclusion agreed with Hegel's or not. "It is impossible to say to what extent this proposition coincides, or does not coincide, with his opinions ; for whatever truth there may be in Hegel, it is certain that his meaning cannot be wrung from him by any amount of mere reading, any more than the whisky which is in bread . . . can be extracted by squeezing the loaf into a tumbler. He requires to be distilled, as all philosophers do more or less — but Hegel to an extent which is unparalleled. A much less intellectual effort would be required to find out the truth for oneself than to understand his exposition of it." l Ferrier does not exaggerate the difficulty of historical exegesis; for it is true not only that the great philosophies require to be distilled, but that they also require to be translated from the terms of their own traditional context to the terms of another. Moreover there must always be a large marginal error in any such interpretation. This being the case, it is not only gratuitous, but suicidal, to add the difficulties of this problem to the difficulties of each special philosophical problem. IV REALISM AS A CONSTRUCTIVE PHILOSOPHY As is almost universally the case with conscious and methodical criticism, realism finds itself committed to certain positive beliefs. The very act of criticism itself cannot but define, however broadly and tentatively, the outline of a general philosophy. Thus, the grounds on which realism rejects subjectivism determine to some extent the superstructure which is to be reared in its place ; while the very fact of the rejection of subjectivism excludes one of the leading metaphysical alternatives, and gives heightened emphasis to the alternatives that remain. 1 Ferrier. Institutes of Metaphysics, 96-97. 32 INTRODUCTION 1. Perhaps the most notable feature of a realistic philosophy is the emancipation of metaphysics from epistemology.1 This means that the nature of things is not to be sought primarily in the nature of knowledge. It does not follow that a realist may not be brought in the end to conclude that moral or spiritual principles dominate the existent world, but only that this conclusion is not to be reached by arguing from the priority of knowledge over its objects. Moral- ism and spiritualism must take their chance among various hy- potheses ; and the question of their truth is to be determined by the place of such principles among the rest within the world. The general fact that whatever the world be judged to be, it is at any rate so judged, and therefore an object of cognition, is to be ig- nored ; and one is left to decide only whether on empirical grounds one may fairly judge the world to be spiritual or moral in part only, or on the whole. It will be seen at once that the chief ground on which a spiritualistic or ethical metaphysics has latterly been urged is removed. But at the same time the metaphysical sig- nificance of life, consciousness, and morality as facts among facts is at once increased ; and these may now be employed for the formulation of hypotheses that are at least pragmatic and verifiable. 2. Again, in rejecting anti-intellectualism and espousing the analytical method, realism is committed to the rejection of all mystical philosophies. This holds of all philosophies that rely on immediacy for a knowledge of complexness ; of all philosophies that regard the many in one as a mystery that can be resolved only by an ineffable insight. A neo-realist recognizes no ultimate immediacies nor non-relational nor indefinable entities, except the simples in which analysis terminates. The ultimate terms of knowledge are the terms that survive an analysis that has been carried as far as it is possible to carry it ; and not the terms which possess simplicity only because analysis has not been applied to them. Such a course of procedure is fatal, not only to a mystical universalism in which the totality of things is resolved into a mo- ment of ecstasy, but also to those more limited mysticisms in which i Cf. below, No. I. REALISM AS A CONSTRUCTIVE PHILOSOPHY 33 complexes such as substance, will, activity, life, energy or power, are regarded despite the obvious manifoldness of their characters, as nevertheless fused and inarticulate. It follows that neo-realism rejects all philosophies in which metaphysics is sharply divorced from the special sciences, on the ground that while the latter must analyze, specify, and systematize, the former may enjoy a peculiar illumination of its own, in which the true heart of things is made apparent, and the facts and laws of science are reduced to dead abstractions, or mere instrumental artifacts. 3. For several reasons the new realism tends, at least in the present state of knowledge, to be metaphysically pluralistic rather than monistic. Most metaphysical monisms have been based on one or the other of two grounds. The first of these is the internal- ity of relations ; the supposition that the nature of terms contains their relations. It is easy to argue from this premise, that since all things are interrelated, the nature of each contains the nature of all. Realism rejects the premise that all relations are internal, because it is believed that it is contrary to the facts of existence, and to the facts of logic. The second ground of monism is the universality of cognition. The rejection of this is, as we have seen, the very starting-point of realism. Without one or the other of these grounds it is not possible to construct a monism dialectically or a priori. This question also becomes an empirical question, and in lieu of the discovery of a law, or set of postulates that shall explain everything, we must at least remain skeptical. The evi- dence at present available indicates that while all things may per- haps be related, many of these relations are not constitutive or determinative ; that is, do not enter into the explanation of the nature or existence of their terms. 4. Again, the primary polemical contention of realism, its re- jection of subjectivism, has its constructive implications. If cognition is not the universal condition of being, then cognition must take its place within being, on the same plane as space, or number, or physical nature. Cognition, in other words, has its genesis and its environment. When knowledge takes place, there 34 INTRODUCTION is a knower interacting with things. The knower, furthermore, since it cannot legitimately be saved from analysis, and referred to a unique mystical revelation, must take its place in one mani- fold with the things it knows. The difference between knower and known is like the difference between bodies, or states of conscious- ness, or societies, or colors, or any grouping of things whatsoever in the respect that they must be brought into one field of study, and observed in their mutual transactions. In all this it is presupposed that if there is to be knowledge, there must be something there to be known, and something there to know ; ' there ' meaning the field in which their relation obtains. Their correlation is not a basic and universal dichotomy, but only a special type of correlation, having no greater prima fade dignity than the many other correlations which the world exhibits. It is not to be taken in bar» formal terms, but is to be observed con- cretely, and in its native habitat. The realist believes that he thus discovers that the interrelation in question is not responsible for the characters of the thing known. In the first place being known is something that happens to a preexisting thing. The characters of that preexisting thing determine what happens when it is known. Then, in the second place, when the knowing takes place, these characters are at least for the most part undisturbed. If they are disturbed, or modified, then the modification itself has to be explained in terms of certain original characters, as conditions of the modification. So that even if it proved necessary to con- clude that illusion and hallucination are due to modifications of the stimulus by the reacting organism, this very conclusion would imply the preexisting and independent character of the body in which the stimulus originated. 5. In immediate and intimate connection with this doctrine of the independence of things known and the knowing of them, stands another special doctrine — to the effect that the content of knowledge, that which lies in or before the mind when knowledge takes place, is numerically identical with the thing known. Knowledge by intermediaries is not denied, but is made subordi- REALISM AS A CONSTRUCTIVE PHILOSOPHY 35 nate to direct or presentative knowledge. There is no special class of entities, qualitatively or substantively distinguished from all other entities, as the media of knowledge. In the end all things are known through being themselves brought directly into that relation in which they are said to be witnessed or apprehended. In other words, things when consciousness is had of them become themselves contents of consciousness; and the same things thus figure both in the so-called external world and in the manifold which introspection reveals. 6. Finally, because he regards analysis and conception as means of access to reality, and not as transformations or falsifications of it, and because he asserts the independence of reality in the know- ing of it, the neo-realist is also a Platonic realist. He accords full ontological status to the things of thought as well as to the things of sense, to logical entities as well as physical entities, or to sub- sistents as well as existents. 7. In short, for realists, knowledge plays its part within an in- dependent environment. When that environment is known it is brought into direct relations with some variety of agency or pro- cess, which is the knower. The knower however is homogeneous with the environment, belonging to one cosmos with it, as does an attracting mass, or physical organism, and may itself be known as are the things it knows. The world is of an articulate structure that is revealed by analysis, consisting of complexes, like bodies, persons, and societies, as well as of simples. The simple con- stituents of the world comprise both sensible qualities and logical constants. Both enter into the tissue of fact, and both possess an inherent and inalienable character of their own. There is no safe refuge from this conclusion in any abandonment of intellec- tual rigor. Hence all speculative versions of the world that re- quire the withholding of analysis, or that depend on the unique and preeminent status of the act of cognition, must be rejected, no matter how eagerly they may be desired for the justification of faith. They must be rejected in favor of such hypotheses as may be formulated in terms of the evident composition of the 36 INTRODUCTION known world, and verified by its actual interrelations, history, and trend. These conclusions in the aggregate can scarcely be said to be negative. It is true that they constitute neither a complete phi- losophy, nor, even so far as they go, an absolutely systematic phi- losophy. But that a philosophy should be absolutely systematic in the sense of being deducible from one principle is itself a philo- sophical doctrine that the realist is by no means prepared to adopt. Moreover that his philosophy should be as yet incomplete is, to the realist at least, a wholesome incentive, rather than a ground for uneasiness. There are endless special philosophical questions to which there is no inevitable realistic answer, such questions as mind and body, teleology, the good, and freedom; and there is as yet no general realistic philosophy of life, no characteristic verdict on the issues of religion. Nevertheless, the foundations and the scaffolding of the realistic universe are already built ; and it is even possible for some to live in it and feel at home. REALISM AND THE SPECIAL SCIENCES 1. IT is the earnest hope of those who have identified themselves with this movement, that it may afford a basis for a more profit- able intercourse with the special sciences than that which has lat- terly obtained. There are common problems which have been hitherto obscured by a radical difference of method, and an in- commensurability of terms. So long as philosophy is simply the exploitation of a unique and supreme insight of its own, it remains either irrelevant to the special sciences or, through its claim of superiority, a source of irritation and an object of suspicion. Such has, to some extent, at least, been the case during the later philo- sophical regime. Idealists have benevolently assimilated science to a universal consciousness ; irrationalists have appealed to revela- tion for insight that overrules and makes naught of all the hard- REALISM AND THE SPECIAL SCIENCES 37 won truths of science. In either case, science is not helped by philosophy, but after being allowed to do the work of truth finding, is graciously assigned to headquarters labeled ' Appearance ' or ' Mere Description/ where it may enjoy the patronage of a superior. Realism advances no all-inclusive conception under which science as a body may be subsumed ; it claims no special revelation, and asks no immunity from the pains of observation and analysis. What is thus lost of eminence and authority, may, it is hoped, be made up by a more cordial and profitable association with fellow-workers in a common task. For, after all, the division of the disciplines is less significant than the identity of problems and the singleness of purpose that should animate all rigorous seekers after knowledge. Consciousness, life, infinity, and continuity are genuine and identical topics of investigation, whether they happen to be alluded to by psychologists, biologists, logicians, and mathematicians, or by philosophers. And it is reasonable to hope that the difference of training and aptitude between the special scientist and the philosopher should yield a summation of light, rather than misunderstanding and confusion. 2. Thus psychology, for example, has for its very subject mat- ter the concrete process of consciousness, and is therefore vitally concerned in anything true which philosophy has to say about consciousness in general. But the alleged discovery of subjectiv- ism, that all things are mental, is so untrue to the phenomena on which psychology has to work, that this science has been brought thereby to a peculiar state of embarrassment. In the concrete processes of perception and cognition, the corpus vile of psychology, the stimuli, howsoever 'mental' they may be in some last and remote analysis, are assuredly not mental in the sense in which the correlated sensations and ideas are so. Precisely because the psychologist has to accept the direct evidence for the existence of particular minds, he can take no part in the conspiracy to make of mind a universal predicate. The result is that idealism has meant nothing to the actual psychologist, who has in his laboratory remained a Cartesian dual- 38 INTRODUCTION 1st. And it is unmistakable that the results of the study of the soul are to-day, and have been through the last three centuries, read off and tabulated in terms of two substances — matter and mind. Sensations and ideas, alleged to be peculiar and private to each percipient, are conceived as invisible pawns which are cor- related one-to-one with the ' brain-cells ' or other cerebral structures, and are superfluous to the actual processes of the brain in spite of frantic efforts to assign to them some regulative function; and they have none but the most chimerical and unstatable relations to the outer objects which these pawns are said to represent. The supposed need of interpreting the results of empirical psychology, or rather of 'observing' all mental processes in terms of two sub- stances, has thoroughly stultified the science as a whole. The artificial and unsupportable situations to which this course has led are numerous, but one in particular is so preposterous and unendurable that it alone would demand a complete revision of the current 'presuppositions' of psychology. This is the concrete situation when two persons are making a psychological experiment. One is called the experimenter, the other the observer or 'subject,' and between them lie the instruments for giving stimuli and re- cording results. The experimenter, by hypothesis, has direct and immediate knowledge of these instruments and in particular of the stimuli which he employs. By hypothesis the observer, al- though similarly a human being with the same gift of cognition, has not a direct or immediate apprehension of these instruments and stimuli, but this observer's knowledge is limited to the field of invisible pawns which 'represent' the stimuli, and which en- joy an otherwise inscrutable status of one-to-oneness with some structures within the observer's skull. So the situation is inter- preted, until presently the two experimenters exchange their rolls, whereupon by a process of magic the just-now observer acquires a direct apprehension of the instruments of stimulation, the scales have fallen from his eyes and are adjusted to the other man's, whose conscious field now shrivels and is merely the fitful flux of the in- tracerebral and invisible pawns. REALISM AND THE SPECIAL SCIENCES 39 This is the situation which attends every psychological experi- ment in which two persons take part. It is absurd, and can be mitigated only by a theory which gives a satisfactory epistemologi- cal status to the 'outer objects' which are the terms common to all human experiences. Neither dualism nor idealism provides such a status. This condition of things is sufficient to induce the psychologist to look toward realism; and yet this is merely one of several insupportable results attendant on a dualistic psychology. In general, it may be said that any argument which makes dualism indefensible in philosophy makes it concretely intolerable in psychology. Psychology has not yet found the right fundamental categories, and will not find them as long as dualism continues to hold sway. Meanwhile its particular findings lie accumulated in incoordinated heaps and investigators are beginning to sense an impasse, and are somewhat inconsequently turning away to various forms of an ' applied ' science. 3. A similar state of things exists in biology ; for here a real- istic philosophical basis is even more clearly presupposed. Indeed, the realistic point of view and all its fundamental propositions may be served on the biologist as a mandamus; for to him are assigned such problems as the origins of life, the origins of species, the man- ners of growth, of variation, and of adaptation. Now each and every one of these problems presents a situation wherein there is an environment independent of a given creature which is being affected by that environment and is, in turn, manipulating itself and parts of the environment. Such a world is realistic ; it is no piece of human imagery, and its texture is made of other stuff than mere thoughts. It is full of minds which it has somehow made and which it, by a mere invisible lesion, can destroy. As with the world, so with the organisms in it. They are not the products of the minds they bear. Although these minds do not even suspect the form and flux of their sustaining organs, yet the latter operate, day and night, indifferent to that ignorance. They are as independent of the mind as is the wind which sighs around the house while the mind sleeps. 40 INTRODUCTION It is true that many biologists look with favor upon idealistic doctrines, which, if accepted, would lead to absurdities. They have applied them only half-heartedly though and thereby be- fuddled many questions, notably that of vitalism versus mechan- ism. So far have some of them gone with the doctrine that things are 'mental constructs,' that they have projected conscious intel- ligence the whole organic process. But they cannot doubt that an organism is needed to produce a 'mental state.' Thus Pauly cannot understand how an organism could ever 'grow' eyes, unless the cause of the growth also had eyes. Nothing, he vir- tually argues, can be done unless the deed is known beforehand in detail ; though to know it, the knower behind the organism must in turn have a perceiving mechanism. It is to avoid such bewil- derment that realism wishes to join hands with the cautious biol- ogists. 4. If realism can afford assistance and clarification to psychology and biology, this is no less the case with logic and the mathemati- cal sciences. At the present time these latter sciences suffer chiefly from a confusing admixture of psychology. This confusion takes two forms, as illustrated by the case of logic. On the one hand, logic as a science of such entities as terms, propositions, propositional functions, etc., is confused with the study of the art and processes of thought. On the other hand, logic as a science of implication and necessity is confused with the study of the his- torical genesis of knowledge. Realism frees logic as a study of objective fact from all accounts of the states or operations of mind. For the realist there are empirical grounds for holding that the object known is independent of and may be dissimilar to the cog- nitive process. Cognition can be eliminated. It is discovery. Accordingly, the realist is an open-minded empiricist. He stands quite ready to find and to admit that anything may be a fact, that any kind of entity may exist, or subsist. The only limitations are a posteriori. For the realist, the study of the knowing process is only one of many fields of investigation. Logic, arithmetic, and mathematics in general are sciences which can be pursued quite REALISM AND THE SPECIAL SCIENCES 41 independently of the study of knowing. The entities with which they deal are not physical ; nor are they mental. They are sub- sistents in that they are entities notwithstanding this fact. Thus these sciences investigate neither physical nor mental entities, but have to do with an independent and objective field of their own. 5. It is necessary that philosophy should raise the questions of epistemology, if only in order to assign them a subordinate place. It will not do to ignore the fact of knowledge itself. Sooner or later, the knower must take himself into the account and become conscious of that inward relation to a subjective background which, in the first objective or outward intent of knowledge, is naturally overlooked. Realism is not a naive or blind neglect of the prob- lem. If realism concludes, as it does, that the knower himself may, in the great majority of cases, be disregarded, and the object be explained in its own terms, it is only after due consideration of the matter. The right so to disregard the subjective conditions of knowledge is an achievement of critical reflection. And it is an achievement of no small moment; for it at once establishes the full rights of all special branches of knowledge. Philosophy must, it is true, now abandon its supposed privilege of radically transforming all results which have been reached with- out taking knowledge into account. Philosophy can no longer condemn such results as necessarily and universally false, or re- place them with a higher esoteric truth, which is revealed only to the initiated. The disregard of epistemological considerations which is characteristic of special investigations is now justified. But what philosophy loses in prerogative, it gains in the improve- ment of its relations with other branches of knowledge. It may now employ the results of the special sciences as they stand. This is true not only of the physical sciences, but of the moral sciences ; and not only of scientists in the professional sense, but of all ob- servers and investigators who have anything to report concerning the state of things in this common world. In other words, once subjectivism and mysticism are discredited, the work of philosophy 42 INTRODUCTION becomes continuous with that of all who have chosen to limit more narrowly the field of their labors. There will always remain a certain difference of procedure between philosophers and spe- cialists. Philosophers will be looked to for breadth of generaliza- tion, for refinement of criticism, and for the solution of such prob- lems as are peculiarly connected with the limits of generalization and criticism. But, even so, the task of philosophy is not radi- cally different from that of the special knowledges. It lies on the same plane, or in the same field. It is a difference of degree and not of kind ; a difference like that between experimental and theo- retical physics, between zoology and biology, or between juris- prudence and political science. Thus, realism proposes that philosophy should abandon for all time that claim to the hereditary exclusive possession of truth which was made in the first days of its youthful arrogance. Though philosophy has until now clung tenaciously to that dualism of knowledge by which Parmenides assigned to philosophy "the un- shaken heart of persuasive truth," and left for the less privileged workers in the field of empirical facts only "the opinions of mortals in which is no true belief at all"; it is the conviction of those who have undertaken the present volume that the way of all mortal opinion, in so far as it is honest and attested by evidence, is the way of truth. THE EMANCIPATION OF METAPHYSICS FROM EPISTEMOLOGY THE EMANCIPATION OF METAPHYSICS FROM EPISTEMOLOGY BY WALTER T. MARVIN I THE ISSUE BETWEEN DOGMATISM AND CRITICISM 1. THE purpose of this essay is to present some arguments in opposition to the belief, held by many philosophers, that the science which investigates the nature, the possibility, and the limits of knowledge is fundamental to all other sciences and to all other scientific procedure, and in particular that this science either is metaphysics or is fundamental to metaphysics.1 As a preliminary to our discussion we must clearly understand what is meant by "one science being fundamental to another." To an inquiry concerning the meaning of the words "one science is fundamental to another," three answers appear to be offered. First, one science is fundamental to another when it is logi- cally prior; and by logical priority is meant that relation which holds between a proposition and its necessary condition. Thus if A implies B but B does not imply A, then B is the necessary condition of A ; for A's truth depends upon B's truth. That is, should B prove to be false, A must be false : and though A be false, still B may prove true; for we are saying merely that A's truth is a sufficient condition of B's truth, and are not maintain- ing that it is the only condition, or a necessary condition. For example, let us assume it to be true that if the tissues of a man's 1 Under the term metaphysics I include two subjects : (a) the study of the logical foundations of science ; (6) the theory of reality. Here and throughout this essay I mean by the words, theory of reality, any collection of fundamental existential propositions and of high existential generalizations. 45 46 METAPHYSICS AND EPISTEMOLOGY body absorb a certain amount of arsenic, he must die, that there is no preventing cause either known or unknown. Then evi- dently for it to be true that this man's body has absorbed such an amount of arsenic, it must be true that the man is dead ; whereas the mere fact of his death does not prove that many another pos- sible cause is not the actual cause. In short, "the man is dead" is logically prior to the proposition, the tissues of his body have absorbed the required quantity of arsenic. But let us illustrate specifically the logical priority of one science to another. Much of mathematics is logically prior to mechanics and physics, since much of these latter sciences could prove false without thereby indicating any errors in our pure mathematical theories; but should it be found that arithmetic, the calculus, and elemen- tary geometry are false, evidently our mechanical and physical theories, based as they are upon these sciences, and being in great part explicit deductions from them, would fall to the ground. Of course there may be other, as yet totally unknown, ways by which mechanics and physics can be demonstrated; but accord- ing to our present knowledge, unless a large part of mathematics is true, mechanics and physics must be false. If then we accept the foregoing as the meaning of the word 'fundamental/ we get as the first answer to our question : In calling the theory of knowl- edge fundamental, the philosopher means that it is logically prior to all other knowledge. 2. The second answer offered appears to be different, though a closer scrutiny may reveal the presence of the same conviction. "The theory of knowledge is fundamental," means not only that the epistemologist can ascertain through his science the limits of possible knowledge, but especially that he can do so without studying the various special sciences or the history of science and of scientific discovery, or without in any way going for informa- tion beyond the territory of his own science. In other words, it is maintained that there is a science of the possibility of knowl- edge which is not an induction from men's scientific experience during the centuries of civilization nor from the sciences as they ISSUE BETWEEN DOGMATISM AND CRITICISM 47 are now known, but which is a direct, independent, and final study of the nature and limits of knowledge. Indeed, it is held that unless we have proven in this way the possibility of any special science, such a science is mere dogmatism ; and therefore that he only is a critical scientist who does not attempt to inves- tigate until he proves to himself by the theory of knowledge that what he hopes to discover and to explain is a possible object of knowledge. Of course the writer has in mind especially Kant and his ' Cri- tique of Pure Reason.' He it was who taught, as no other man has taught, that dogmatism and criticism are forever irreconcilable, that one science, the science of the possibility of knowledge, can ascertain what are and what are not problems which the human mind can solve. He thought that the older metaphysicians, who were either ignorant or careless of these matters, were led hopelessly into error precisely because they undertook to solve their problems before they wrote or studied a critique of pure reason. Moreover, note well; this critique of pure reason is not a his- tory of the successes and failures of scientists, nor is it a summary of what in the course of human history have proved solvable and insolvable problems. Rather it is a direct study of the nature of knowledge in the abstract and of the behavior of the human in- tellect; and its conclusions are said to be drawn from this study without the aid of the other sciences. On this account its results are believed to be independent of the special sciences and au- thoritative over them ; whereas if it drew its information from them or were itself a mere induction from human experience, it would be admittedly a vicious circle. 3. The third answer informs us that in calling the theory of knowledge fundamental the philosopher asserts that this science can enable us to ascertain the validity of the special sciences and of their methods, and in certain respects at least can enable us even to correct their results. For example, if a science offers us a solution of some problem which we know to be insolvable, 48 METAPHYSICS AND EPISTEMOLOGY or asserts what is beyond the possibility of human knowledge, we can infer at once that this part of such a science must be in- valid. But this is by no means all that is referred to in the third meaning of the word, 'fundamental.' Rather we are given to understand that the theory of knowledge offers us information regarding reality, and that this information is of great value in two respects ; it is more certainly true than are the results of the special sciences, and it is a means of refuting, correcting, and limiting these results. For example, if a study of the nature of knowledge shows that the universe must be an organic unity; it can be inferred that should the sciences indicate the opposite, they are at the best only relatively or partly true. Again, if a study of knowledge shows that only mental contents can be known, that an object to be known must be part of the mind's experi- ence; then it can be inferred directly without further evidence from science that reality as far as it is knowable must be the experience of some mind. Then if in addition the theory of knowl- edge shows that whatever is essentially unknowable cannot be real; we reach the conclusion, reality as such is the experience of one or more minds, and only that. Hence, should popular opinion and scientific inference assert in opposition to this that things exist which cannot be experienced or which belong to no one's experience, such doctrines would be subject to correction by our fundamental science. Still again, if it be true, as some epistemologists have taught, that the mind in knowing gives a form to the objects known and consequently that whatever is known must have this form or structure; then their science can lay down for all time to come the main outlines of the world as the possible object of scientific research. Should the physicist or any other scientist ever quar- rel with this outline furnished by our philosopher, it will be our duty to inquire whether or not he is a student of the theory of knowledge and has made a discovery in that field. Should it prove that he is not an epistemologist, but just a physicist, mathe- matician, or chemist; our philosopher will tell him that he is not ISSUE BETWEEN DOGMATISM AND CRITICISM 49 competent to talk about ultimate reality, for his science may indeed give useful information, but cannot give any independent and fundamental insight into what is and what is not ultimately real. For example, it has been claimed by one epistemologist or another that the world as an object of knowledge must be a three-dimensional spatial system, a temporal system, a causal system, a system of sense impressions, a society of minds, an organic unity, an infinite and perfect personal mind, a divine language by which God sends us messages, a battlefield created by the mind wherein the will may fight for the moral ideals, the dreary, hopeless outcome of the struggles of an impersonal, blind and restless will, an evolution of an absolute mind. Negatively it has been held by one philosopher or another as the result of his study of the nature of knowledge, that matter does not truly exist, that colors and sounds, heat and cold, do not exist outside the mind, that scientific laws are not truly parts of nature, that the real world cannot be known. 4. Let us sum up briefly these three meanings of the state- ment, "the theory of knowledge is fundamental," in the following propositions: First, the theory of knowledge is logically prior to all other knowledge; secondly, one can by a direct study of the knowing process infer the limits of possible knowledge; and thirdly, the student of epistemology can give us, independently of all other sciences, a theory of reality. By no means do I claim that these three propositions cannot be and should not be further analyzed and reduced to one, namely to the first ; rather, I believe precisely this: but for the purpose of the present argument it is better to leave them as they stand. 5. In opposition to these beliefs in the fundamental charac- ter of the theory of knowledge, this essay will support directly or indirectly the truth of the following propositions : (a) first, that the theory of knowledge is not logically fundamental, that on the con- trary its logical position is posterior to many of the special sciences, such as physics and biology ; (&) secondly, that the theory of knowledge does not enable us to show, except inductively and em- 50 METAPHYSICS AND EPISTEMOLOGY pirically, either what knowledge is possible or how it is possible, or again, what are the limits of human knowledge; (c) thirdly, that no light is thrown by the theory of knowledge upon the na- ture of the existent world or upon the fundamental postulates and generalizations of science, except in as far as the knowledge of one natural event or object enables us sometimes to draw inferences regarding certain others; (d) fourthly, that epistemology does not give us a theory of reality, on the contrary, -it assumes one ; (e) finally, that it neither solves metaphysical problems nor is it the chief source of such problems. One may express all of this affirmatively as follows. I shall try to show three things: (a) first, that the theory of knowledge is one of the special sciences, that it studies knowledge as a natural event and in virtually the same way and by the same methods as biology studies life or physics light ; (6) secondly, that as such a science, it assumes the formulae of logic and the results of several special sciences, such as physics and biology; (c) and finally, that logic, metaphysics, and some existential sciences are logically prior to the theory of knowledge. 6. In short, the general conclusion which I shall draw is that metaphysics is logically prior to the theory of knowledge and that it is not peculiarly indebted to this science either for its problems or for their solution. If this conclusion is true, then metaphysics should be completely emancipated from epistemology ; for the sway that this science has held over metaphysics from the days of Locke to our own time is a thoroughly unconstitutional assumption of authority. Thus in a certain respect I am urging a return to the old days of the seventeenth century, to the days of Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz, to the method that Kant con- demned as dogmatism. Indeed, let us for the sake of brevity ac- cept throughout this essay Kant's terms to indicate the two oppos- ing tendencies. In a narrow and technical meaning of the words, the one tendency is dogmatic and its doctrines are dogmatism,1 1 It should be distinctly understood by the reader that the word dogmatism is used throughout this essay in the narrow and precise sense above denned. The EPISTEMOLOGY NOT FUNDAMENTAL 51 whereas the teachings of the opposed tendency are criticism and their defenders are criticists. II THE THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE IS NOT LOGICALLY FUNDA- MENTAL 1. THE first and most prominent tenet of the criticist may be stated thus : Inasmuch as all sciences are cases of knowl- edge, the science which investigates knowledge as such is funda- mental and is, both in fact and by right, a critique of all science. Underlying this doctrine the dogmatist finds, or at least suspects, name is taken from Kant's Critique of Pure Reason where, whatever else it may mean, it denotes the contradictory of what Kant calls criticism. Unfortunately, the word has other associations in Kant's mind and in the mind of the student of Kant ; for it sometimes means specifically the rationalistic ontology of the Cartesian and Leibrdzian philosophers, whereas neo-realism differs radically from this phi- losophy. For example, many neo-realists have a strong tendency toward an extreme empiricism and toward an abandonment of the substance-attribute notion as a fundamental notion in metaphysics. Again, neo-realism is epistemological monism ; whereas the Cartesians were epistemological dualists, holding to a representative rather than a presentative theory of perception. Finally, a modern dogmatism must of necessity differ from that of the earlier centuries just because it has behind it two centuries of experience with criticism. That is, it is consciously and de- liberately dogmatic, whereas the earlier dogmatism was naive and was therefore easily misled into idealism and its so-called criticism. But in spite of these unfortu- nate associations I believe the names dogmatism and criticism not only appropriate but enlightening ; for I think the neo-realistic movement to be a reaction against the whole enterprise of Locke, Kant, and their followers to get at a fundamental science and not merely against their idealism. That is, neo-realism is not only a different theory of knowledge but, what is more important for metaphysics, a different doctrine as to the place of epistemology in the hierarchy of the sciences. As the names realism and idealism do not point out this difference clearly; I prefer the names dogmatism and criticism, which, if taken in their generic meanings as given by Kant, certainly indicate precisely this difference. Indeed, I would go further ; for many contemporary realists are criticists, and it is at least conceivable, no matter how remarkable, that some dogmatists may be idealists. My points may be summed up briefly in the following two sentences. Dogmatism is the con- tradictory of criticism and defines neo-realism negatively or by exclusion. Chiefly and perhaps only in this respect is neo-realism a return to seventeenth century philosophy. 52 METAPHYSICS AND EPISTEMOLOGY two errors, on the one hand the assumption of a false theory re- garding the nature of logic, and on the other a failure to distin- guish between two uses of the word 'knowledge,' that which denotes the act of knowing and that which refers to the truths or propositions known. 2. To many philosophers logic still seems to be a science of the knowing process, or more precisely, a science of the laws of thought, that is, of the rules dictated by the mind's own nature and obeyed by us whenever we think correctly; whereas logic is nothing of the sort. The formulae of logic are no more laws of thought than is the undulatory theory of light, the Mendelian law of heredity, or for that matter a recipe for cake or even an adding machine. Logic gives us no information in particular regarding the mind or the thinking process; and the logician's views on such subjects might be quite erroneous without leading him astray within his proper field. 3. What then is logic ? And I mean by logic not only the re- sults of recent study, which the reader may or may not value highly, but also the ancient doctrines to be found in the writings of Aris- totle and in the textbooks of past centuries. The logician offers us, as does any other scientist, information regarding certain terms and their relations. Some of these terms are classes, and some of these relations are the relations obtaining between classes and their members or between one class and other classes. Further, some terms studied in logic are propositions, and propositions are found to be related in a way called implication. Therefore the logician tries to learn the ways in which one proposition can be related by implication to another. Finally, logic deals with a number of fundamentally different sorts of relation. As the logi- cian puts it, some are transitive, some intransitive, some sym- metrical, some asymmetrical, and so on. 4. Now in all of this logic is studying something non-mental in the same sense as does mathematics or chemistry. There are in the world about us classes and these classes are related. There are such things as truths and falsehoods and these as such are EPISTEMOLOGY NOT FUNDAMENTAL 53 related to one another. Moreover, they are so related quite apart from any question of human existence or human thought. " Two plus two equals fourteen," was false fifty million years ago ; and the fact that it was false, made the world of that day a very different world from what it would otherwise have been. Thus to the best of our knowledge, the fact that one proposition implies another is not merely a pleasant and playful thought of this man or that, but it is a downright serious matter. It seems to deter- mine what happens in this world about us, it seems to determine whether a man shall die or live, shall be born or not be born, shall be happy or utterly wretched. It seems to determine even whether a solar system shall go along peacefully and evolve habit- able planets, or shall go to smash and end in chaos. There may be some sense in which all of these things are mental; that is, some sense in which astronomy, physics, chemistry, biology, geology, and what not other science is a study of human knowl- edge and of the knowing process. All well and good; if such be the case, no doubt logic is so too; but if in other respects they are not such a study, then neither is logic. The nature of the physical universe depends upon whether or not logic is true as genuinely as it does upon the truth of this or that physical theory. Therefore the logician has a right to say: "When I study classes and their relations, or propositions and their relations, I am studying aspects of the world about me as truly as does the physi- cist when he studies the nature of light, heat, gravity, and elec- tricity." 5. "But," you ask, "is not logic the science or art of correct reasoning? And is not reasoning a mental process?" No, logic is not. Of course there is such a study or art, and of course there is excellent authority for the use of the word logic as the name of this art. But the art called logic, when examined critically from the point of view of the pure sciences, is a conglomerate of many sciences applied to solving one type of practical problem. In short, it is the application of information from many scien- tific sources. It draws on pure logic, it draws on psychology, it 54 METAPHYSICS AND EPISTEMOLOGY draws on mathematics; indeed, I decline to mention the pure science upon which it should not draw. 6. Yet it may be protested, "In all our reasoning we use logic, therefore logic is the science of reasoning." Such an argument is fallacious, and what is more, its conclusion is false. To make a long story short, we must define what is meant in this argument by the word 'use,' and we must decline from the start to reckon by percentage of use whether or not this or that science or part of a science is a study of the knowing process. Do we in our reason- ing use logic in a different way from that in which we use mathe- matics, physics, chemistry, or astronomy? Now if we do not, and if the only difference is that we use some parts of logic every time we reason, why should we then draw the line at one hundred per cent (really a lesser per cent for parts of logic may be used quite infrequently and we should take the average) and not at forty-five per cent? Evidently the man who believes logic to be a science of reasoning is not thinking of percentage of use. Rather he holds that the use our reasoning makes of logic is differ- ent from the use our minds make of mathematics or chemistry. It is then all a question of the meaning of the word use. How do we use logic in our reasoning? I reply, in the same way in which we use physics. How is that? We make use of the laws or propositions of physics as premises or as formulae for whose variables we substitute constants. Let me illustrate. I want to know how far a projectile will go if it leaves the ground at a given angle and at a given velocity. Physics gives me formulae from which, if I use as premises along with the given conditions also used as premises, I can infer the proposition which I wish to know. Again, mathematics tells me (a + ft)2 = a2 + 2 ab + b2. I want to know the square of 27. How then do I use (in my reasoning) this information? We substitute, let us say, for a 20 and for b 7; that is, we substitute constants for the variables in the equa- tion. Thus (20 + 7)2 = 400 + 280 + 49 = 729. Hence to use physics or any other exact or natural science in our reasoning is to adopt its propositions as premises, Now is the same thing EPISTEMOLOGY NOT FUNDAMENTAL 55 true when we use logic in our reasoning? It is. The results or truths of logic are assertions, as we have said, regarding the re- lations of classes and propositions. Further, these results of logic are usually formulse, that is, propositions whose terms are variables. Thus, roughly stated, if any class a is contained in another class b, and if this class 6 in turn is contained in a third class c, then the first class a is contained in the third class c ; or more precisely stated, [(a